|
Theotropic Boundaries
for Epistemological Defeasibility of a Mauvaise Foi:
Mathematics and K- to K+
By Dallas F. Bell, Jr.
Abstract: Defeasibility of a belief, especially a mauvaise foi, indicates a
process that exposes vulnerability to a positive epistemic status. The laws of probability act as coherence
constraints on rational levels of beliefs (T. Bayes). The epistemology of religion includes
evidentialism where belief is made plausible from justification of the
proportional evidence. Those
justifications can be found in visual mathematical modeling (L. Kirby, J.
Paris, and R. Goodstein) and explained by precise mathematical symbols. The common concept of infinity (G.
Cantor, C. Wickramasinghe, and C. Tapp) may be used as a tool to demonstrate
core rational ideas which provide theotropic
boundaries (A. Herschel and P. de Man).
Proof from the resultant sequences (I. Kant, É. Tempier, and F. Nietzsche) has the potential to cause
systematic change from K- to K+ gradients in the territories of knowledge.
Keywords: theotropic boundaries, epistemological
defeaters, coherence, mathematical infinity.
Man is not at peace with his fellow man because he is not at peace with
himself:
he is not at peace with himself, because he is
not at peace with God.
Thomas Merton (1915-1968)
Defeasibility of a belief, especially a mauvaise foi, indicates a
process that exposes anomian vulnerability to a positive epistemic status. Thomas Bayes (1701-1761) proposed a
formal apparatus for inductive logic and introduced a self-defeat test for
epistemological rationality. He
used the laws of probability as coherence constraints on rational levels of
beliefs. Coherentism is a belief,
or a set of beliefs, justified as the belief coheres with a set of beliefs
forming a coherent set.
The epistemology of religion may include evidentialism where
a belief is plausible from justification of the proportional evidence. The result can be theotropic (Gr. God,
to turn). Abraham J. Herschel (1907-1972)
defined this term as "turning toward God," whereas Paul de Man (1919-1983) implied
it to mean a "turning away from God."
Sheila Embleton, Vice-President Academic, Provost and
Professor of graduate programs in linguistics at York University, observed that things are very seldom equal between
participants of communication exchanges, as there are always age, gender,
social/economic, and hierarchical differences. She points out that mathematical
equations cannot convey cultural, religious, philosophical (etc.) concepts well
at all, whereas sentences (even if it takes many of them) can.[1]
Noam Chomsky said language is a set of sentences composed of
finite length from a finite set of elements. If it is said "seven is the square root
of forty-nine," "seven is less than nine," and "seven
is a prime number," is it known what the meaning of "is" is? The first "is" says the object "seven"
and the object "the square root of forty-nine" are equal, so "is" means equal. The second sentence is an adjectival
phrase where "less than nine" is specifying a property that numbers may or may
not have. The third sentence means
seven is an example of a prime number.
Generally, the language of mathematics uses precise symbols
that are less culturally dependant than words which
can be barriers to understanding.
For example, the three sentences in the preceding paragraph could be
mathematically expressed as 7 = √49, 7 < 9, and P(n) where n is a positive integer, meaning n or 7 is a prime. That
mathematical exchange of the lack of information (K-) to having the new
information (K+) with symbols obviously seems to be more efficient than
conventional sentences of words.
The epistemological sequence into territories of knowledge
is a change of the state of K- to a state of K+. Modeling this process assumes a shared
position of common ground of linguistic information. An assertion is likely to encode
presupposition. They are expected
to be common while adding new content, such as 7 = √49 assumes each participant
(the one with the information presented to the one(s) without the information)
understands numbers and what square root means.
In 1982, Laurie Kirby and Jeff Paris[2]
interpreted Reuben Goodstein's 1944 theorem in a hydra game. The Hydra is a finite rooted tree. The goal is to cut off the
branches/nodes of the tree as they grow back a finite number of new branches. If they are continuously cut back
according to the simple rules, the tree will eventually be cut down to the root
ending the game. Kirby explains the
hydra combinatorics shows the relationship of mathematical/logical questions of
unprovability in formal systems begging the question of the need for proof to
know something is true.[3]
In a thermodynamic sense, the hydra game of finite options
can be called a closed system. This
would mean the mass and energy has a beginning and an end, unlike an open
system. A phase transition is
something in transition to something else and not something from nothing. Like empty space, ( ), it is a set containing
nothing, not mass nor energy, or else it is not mathematical empty space. The ultimate open system that must
thermodynamically exist in order to be the first cause of all effects, in our
closed finite system, is a state of infinity.
Aristotle (384 BC – 322 BC) distinguished between
potential infinity (e.g. numbers) and actual infinity (e.g. the Divine). Georg Cantor (1845-1918) treated
infinities not just as potential, but as actual. He indicated a countable infinity plus
another countable infinity is a countable infinity. Christian Tapp points out that we know
from set theory that there are several different infinite numbers, such as
so-called transfinite ordinal numbers, which can be compared with each other so
that there is in fact a sense in which the infinite in the sense of some
infinite number is less than the infinite in the sense of some other infinite
numbers. Those mathematical entities
are not temporal and do not connote change and can be seen as static, which is
a term usually defining something that is unchanged in a world of change.[4]
Chandra Wickramasinghe describes mathematical infinity as
1/x as x approaches progressively closer to unity,[5]
though all numbers have value and do not actually merge as x approaches
zero. Of course, the appearance of
larger number's closeness is due to their ratio of value, such as 1 is twice as
small as 2 but this ratio of value is much smaller with 1,001 and 1,002.
The reality and truth that two objects added to two more
objects equals four objects existed before man could conceive of it. Numbers are purposefully ordered 1, 2, 3
... with their unique values and properties so intellects can communicate with
them in a mathematical/logical language.
This is why it is rationally concluded that the first Causer of all
effects is an infinite state of completeness or wholeness called holiness.[6] Completeness is a property of
infiniteness, Tapp also observed.[7] The change from the status quo or static
state, to use temporal expressions, to creating requires purpose from
intellect. That infinite Intellect
created humans with observable attributes and values of love, mercy, and
justice and thus must also have those properties for completeness. That Being's love, mercy, and justice
etc. would be infinite and immutable as humans finitely attempt to understand
the material and non-material.
Marcus Aurelius[8]
(121 AD – 180 AD) wrote in his Meditations
that whatever happens has been waiting to happen since the beginning of
time. In Plato's (c. 427 BC –
c. 347 BC) Theory of Ideas (Forms), he maintained that all ideas have always
existed. That implies a
Consciousness, pre-existent to man, held and holds those ideas. King Solomon[9] of
Israel wrote whatever the Creator does is forever and nothing can be added to
it. He also noted that there is
nothing new that has not been before.[10] Those assertions maintain that
everything that can happen, within the Creator's will, will eventually
happen. From Aristotle to Immanuel
Kant (1724-1804), this plenitude principle has been accepted as a possibility.[11] Étienne
Tempier (c. 1210 - d. 1279) went further by saying if the Creator could create
something, it should be accepted as having been created. To do otherwise, he concluded, would
artificially limit the Creator and is heresy. But if the Creator could not choose to
limit Himself, He would not be infinite.
For example, the omnipotent Creator could have created more than one
world, but His revelation in Tempier's Bible indicates He made only one.
From these theotropic boundaries, we can see the
epistemological defeaters for the incoherent beliefs that a Creator doesn't
exist or is just a creating force, requiring the most amount of faith for the
most incoherence from the finite human agnostic condition.[12] The next defeater is the belief of the
Creator being a monotheistic god.
That being could not be infinitely complete, due to the need of having
another equal being to equally love and be loved by perfectly before having
created the first cause of all effects.
Furthermore, the epistemological defeater of beliefs for separate
pantheistic gods is evident in that such gods are not co-equal and are thus not
infinitely complete, making them the unholy source of the original sin and
unfit for eternal justice. Smaller
infinities do exist within infinities for numbers but they encompass the set of
infinite numbers and are only part of a whole of numbers. The biblical triune Creator[13]
has a coherent explanation for infinity and original sin
which no other religious system can be said to have, requiring the least
faith for the least incoherence from the finite human agnostic position.
That exclusion process applies the principle for a possible
Creator by eliminating the incoherent monotheistic and pantheistic etc.
alternatives to the Holy Trinity Creator.
If a hydra tree is used to simulate this finite epistemological
sequence, those finite defeaters can be chopped off until the root of the true
Creator is empirically and coherently determined.
That principle means if there are no rational exceptions to
the conclusion that conclusion can be accepted as true. Prime numbers can be found with this
principle. All numbers have weight
due to their value and therefore have infinite existence. They must exist in order of their value
and are infinitely linear. At this
point, they can be seen as a tool for analysis and measurement for communications
between intellects with reasoning ability.
When numbers are examined further, there is a recognizable symmetry of
square roots that increase at a predictable rate as numbers increase and
predictable symmetrical positions of descending degree size of interior angles
as sides increase for polygons.
Prime numbers are generally defined as whole numbers that
have no divisors except 1 and the number itself, such as 3. 1 fits this definition, due to its
unique beginning position with no possibility of whole number divisors. 2 is
technically a prime also due to its proximity to 1. However, it is an even number and is
equally divided into a whole number, 1, which are not
aspects of prime numbers. A natural
number greater than 1 and is not prime is a composite number.
Prime numbers show their individual mass and energy, like
the reality of a black hole, when posed by intellects in mathematical
operations. For example, the prime
of 3 is less than 4, 3 < 4, and the difference between 3 and 4 is 1, 4 -3 =
1. In comparison, 3 has an energy and mass decrease of 1 with 4.
1
|
2
|
3
|
4
|
5
|
6
|
7
|
8
|
9
|
10
|
11
|
12
|
13
|
2
|
4
|
6
|
8
|
10
|
12
|
14
|
16
|
18
|
20
|
22
|
24
|
26
|
3
|
|
9
|
12
|
15
|
18
|
21
|
24
|
27
|
30
|
33
|
36
|
39
|
4
|
|
|
16
|
20
|
24
|
28
|
32
|
36
|
40
|
44
|
48
|
52
|
5
|
|
|
|
25
|
30
|
35
|
40
|
45
|
40
|
55
|
60
|
65
|
6
|
|
|
|
|
36
|
42
|
48
|
54
|
60
|
66
|
72
|
78
|
7
|
|
|
|
|
|
49
|
56
|
63
|
70
|
77
|
84
|
91
|
8
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
64
|
72
|
80
|
88
|
96
|
104
|
9
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
81
|
90
|
99
|
108
|
117
|
10
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
100
|
110
|
120
|
130
|
11
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
121
|
132
|
143
|
12
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
144
|
156
|
13
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
169
|
The gravity of prime numbers can be understood as a having a
necessary connecting pull between the nonprime numbers that surround them as
seen above. The steps to predicting
and quickly proving prime numbers employs what we know about them and excluding
identifiable alternatives. Prime
numbers (in red font above) begin with the base prime of 3 as follows:
|
|
3
|
4
|
5
|
6
|
7
|
8
|
9
|
10
|
11
|
12
|
13
|
14
|
15
|
All multiples of 3 can not be prime
by definition and excludes from possible primes the vertical column numbers
under 3 to infinity (excludes ⅓ of all numbers). Even numbers are divisible by 2 and are
also excluded from possible primes (excludes ½ of all numbers). A pattern is observed with the
horizontal rows below 3. The
possible prime numbers alternate between the second number
in the following row with the first number in the next row to infinity
(excluding ⅔ of all numbers).
In this case, 5, 7, 11, and 13 are prime numbers along with 3. It is obvious that the odd number before
a multiple of 3 and the odd number after a multiple of 3 are candidates to be
prime numbers, such as 5 and 7 that surround 6 or 7
and 11 that surround 9 or 11 and 13 that surround 12.
Possible prime numbers proved to not be prime from primes 5
to 23 are 7 rows which equal 28 possible primes.
23
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
529
|
19
|
|
|
|
|
|
361
|
437
|
17
|
|
|
|
|
289
|
323
|
391
|
13
|
|
|
|
169
|
221
|
247
|
299
|
11
|
|
|
121
|
143
|
187
|
209
|
253
|
7
|
|
49
|
77
|
91
|
119
|
133
|
161
|
5
|
25
|
35
|
55
|
65
|
85
|
95
|
115
|
|
5
|
7
|
11
|
13
|
17
|
19
|
23
|
As numbers get larger the process remains simple. For example, the number 966 is divisible
by 3, 322, and is not prime and its position must be
as follows.
961
|
962
|
963
|
964
|
965
|
966
|
967
|
968
|
969
|
This makes 961, 965, and 967 possible prime numbers. 961 is
divisible by 31 and not a prime.
965 ends with a 5 and so is immediately
identifiable as divisible by 5 and not prime. 967 is not
divisible by smaller prime numbers and is a prime number. Non prime numbers in the position of
possible prime numbers are divisible by prime numbers only with the exception
of the non prime number of 25 which is multiplied by a
prime excluding its sum from being prime.
Take the following examples:
121
|
122
|
123
|
124
|
125
|
126
|
127
|
128
|
129
|
121 is divisible by the prime of
11, 11 times, 11 x 11 = 121, and not prime. 125 is
divisible by the prime of 5, 25 times, 5 x 25 = 125, and not prime. 127 is not
divisible by a prime and is proved to be a prime number. (7 x 25 = 175 and not prime, 11 x 25 =
275 and not prime, 13 x 25 = 325 and not prime etc. etc.)
Simplifying the divisor possibilities of 967 begins with its
square root, 31.096... . Its divisors must be below the lower
prime of this whole number, 31.
Additionally, divisors should begin with the lowest prime number above
3. Since its last number is not a 5
or 0 divisor attempts begin with 7 then proceed to 11, 13, 17, 19, 23, 29 and
ends with 31 x 31 etc. 31 x 31 = 961 which is divisible by itself and is, of course, excluded
from the possibility of being a prime number. The number 967 is then proved to
be a prime.
Another example could be 367. 367 divided by 3 equals 122.3. 3 x 122 = 366. The base of 366 is employed and
indicates possible prime numbers as follows:
361
|
362
|
363
|
364
|
365
|
366
|
367
|
368
|
369
|
365 is obviously divisible by 5 and
not prime. 367, square root of 19.157..., is not divisible by prime numbers below 19 and is
proved prime, 361 is divisible by 19, 19 x 19, and is not prime.
The amount of prime numbers do decrease as numbers grow
larger and have more possible divisors, but Euclid's (c. 325 BC – c. 265
BC) Elements prove their existence to infinity. Prime numbers have rational positions,
predictability and provability.
Irrationality, randomness, and chaos are observations from inadequate
knowledge of what is being observed.
By necessity, the Creator of the first cause of all effects,
with order and mystery observable by man, has purposed options for man to
choose. David Hilbert's (1862-1943)
hotel is not considered a defeater of this probability and does not deny
mathematical infinity (prime numbers etc.) or the biblical account of theology
(omniscience of infinite data held by that Divine data holder etc.).[14]
Gott ist tot (German; God is dead) has been a widely quoted
statement by Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900), who was diagnosed as insane. In Die
fröhliche wissenschaft (The Madman),
Nietzsche continued after saying God is dead, "What water is there to clean ourselves? What
festivals of atonement, what sacred games shall we have to invent? Is not greatness of this deed too great
for us? Must we ourselves not
become gods simply to appear worthy?"
Understanding theology requires effort, as does mathematics which is a subset of theology. Seekers of the laws of nature must
follow the evidence and are ultimately seeking infinite holiness. Nietzsche rejected the Being of
infinity—God. With antimony,
he proceeded to attempt to cohere the human need to be clean from unholiness
(sin), find the path for atonement, redemption and sanctification[15]
by unmerited prevenient grace, and determine who has the holiness that can
forgive hamaratias (sin) and impute[16]
holiness[17]
making man complete.[18] He attempted this without the Creator of
those needs—Sancta Simplicitas of congruous merit. People do not all have the same ability
to see the branches of truth once they cut the tree off at the root. It is said God blinds those that reject
Him.[19] It is the glory of God to conceal a
thing.[20]
Moses recorded biblical atonement is made by blood sacrifice[21]
on altars by Abel,[22]
Noah,[23]
Abraham,[24]
Isaac,[25]
Jacob,[26]
Moses.[27] King Solomon made the temple for
sacrifice.[28] Solomon's temple would be destroyed
long-term around 70 AD. The Messiah
was to suffer for the sins of others occurring around 30 AD.[29] That Prince of Peace[30]
was to be the new atonement sacrifice and the new Temple rising on the third
day occurring three days after crucifixion.[31] The Messiah's death and resurrection[32]
would be testament to the new covenant for atonement.[33] The Creator would not, and can be argued
did not, leave off the means of atonement after Solomon's temple was destroyed
the last time nearly 2,000 years ago, answering Cur Deus Homo.[34] In the pleroma of time,[35]
He would give light to those in darkness and be a guide into the way of peace.[36]
Theology analyzes and proves a threshold for belief for the
past and the future as it bounds what is to be considered good and what is to
be considered evil, while providing purpose for the present. It gives the logical system for epistemology
to see the ways we understand. When
looking at the theotropic boundaries for epistemological defeasibility of a bad
belief or faith, mauvaise foi, mathematics
is a tool for coherence when going from K- to K+.
(S. D. G.)
[1]
Embleton's comments were made in an email exchange with Dallas F. Bell Jr. in December, 2013.
[2] Thanks
to Paris, Professor in the School of Mathematics at Manchester University, and
Andre J. Bauer, Professor
of Computational Mathematics at the University of Ljubljana in Slovenia,
for their assistance during an email exchange with Dallas F. Bell Jr. in December, 2013.
[3] Kirby's,
Professor of mathematics at Baruch College City University of New York,
statement was excerpted from an email exchange with Dallas F. Bell Jr. in December, 2013.
[4] Tapp's,
Professor of philosophy and theology at Ruhr-University Bochum, observations
where made in an email exchange with Dallas F. Bell Jr. during December, 2013.
[5]
Wickramasinghe's, Director of the Buckingham Centre for Astrobiology at the
University of Buckingham and Professor at Cardiff University, comments were
taken from an email exchange with Dallas F. Bell Jr. in December,
2013.
[6] KJV Bible, Lev. 19:2; Hos. 11:9; John 17:11; Acts 2:27.
[8] A Stoic
known for murdering unarmed Christians for their beliefs.
[9] Born c.
989 BC (II Sam. 12:24) and died c. 926 BC (I Kings 11:43).
[11] Other
holders of this principle to some degree were Epicurus (341 BC – 270 BC),
St. Augustine (354 AD – 430 AD), St. Anselm (c. 1033 – 1109),
Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), and Giordano Bruno (1548-1600).
[12] This is
why such a perspective generates ideas like panspermia, held by Sir Fred Hoyle
(1915-2001) and Richard Dawkins etc., or multiverse systems when previously
held explanations of human existence is disproven, such as Darwinian evolution
on Earth (e.g. the absence of species change in fossil records and the
impossibility of DNA code increases etc.).
Those ideas are created to offset the abundance of coherent opposition
and foster an illusion of rationality.
The cognitive dissonance of this belief is the source of relentless
stress from frequent contradictions for which physical sanctions are advocated
against 95% of the world's population that have beliefs with less defeaters, as
seen by the writings and lectures of the so-called new atheists (e.g. Dawkins
has recommended that people that disagree with his belief not be allowed to
attend Oxford University etc. That
would exclude scientists such as Sir Isaac Newton, 1642-1727, Clerk Maxwell,
1831-1879, etc.). This behavior
seeks to gain temporary emotional release from delusional victory over those
they identify as their physical enemies.
[13] Gen. 1:1-3, 26; Is. 40:13, 48:16; Matt. 3:16-17; John 14:26, 15:26.
[14] Thanks
to the office of William Lane Craig, Professor of
philosophy at Biola University's
Talbot School of Theology, for assistance with
this query during December, 2013.
[17] Hebrew kodesh. Greek hagiotes.
[19] Is. 6:10; Jere. 5:21.
[21] Lev. 17:11; Heb. 9:22.
[27] Ex. 24:6-8.
Moses built a tabernacle with an altar, Ex. 26-30.
[29] Ps.
22:16; Matt. 27:35. Is. 53:1-12; I Pet. 1:18-20.
[31] John 2:19-22; Eph. 1:7; Heb. 9:11-14.
[32] Ps.
16:8-11; Acts 2:25-28.
[34] St.
Anselm's book, "Why God Man" (Latin, Cur
Deus Homo), can be found at www.fordham.edu/halsall/basis/anselm-curdeus.asp
[35] Gal. 4:4; Eph. 1:10.
|